The
Place of Criminal Accountability in Transitional Justice:
Reflections After Kosovo
By Richard
Falk, TFF adviser
Reconciling peace and justice in the aftermath of a
criminal regime invariably presents difficult choices
that can only be resolved within the context of each
historical experience. There are no guidelines that can
serve societies that have endured a governing process
that included Crimes against Humanity and gross abuses of
human rights, but are currently making a democratic
transition based on constitutionalism and respect for the
individual. Fashioning an appropriate approach is
rendered more difficult to the extent that the former
regime voluntarily gave up power as part of a bargain
with the democratic opposition, and yet remains on the
scene, even continuing to control the armed forces and
internal police apparatus. The Southern Cone countries of
Chile and Argentina pose this challenge in its sharpest
possible form, but the same type of issue is posed for
many other countries, including South Africa and several
Central American countries.
The complexity of this challenge has been widely
revealed over the course of the last year or so by the
controversy surrounding the arrest of the former Chilean
dictator, Auguste Pinochet. At issue most fundamentally
is whether international standards governing the
accountability of leaders takes precedence over the
implementation of a national bargain in Chile, giving
Pinochet effective immunity, and even a position of
Senator for Life. Extending law to govern crimes of state
has more generally resurfaced in this period as a result
of the end of the cold war, and even more so, the human
abuse arising from the breakup of former Yugoslavia
during the course of the 1990s. For one thing a special
criminal tribunal has been established at The Hague with
authority over such allegations, as well as a parallel
effort arising from the genocidal events that occurred in
Rwanda in 1994. As well, through a transnational
coalition of NGOs in collaboration with a series of
governments, the Rome Treaty was signed in 1998 with the
goal of establishing a permanent international criminal
court. At the same time, there are various negotiations
going forward about trials in Cambodia that address Khmer
Rouge crimes in the 1970s and proposals urging the
indictment of Saddam Hussein.
How can we explain this resurgence of
inter-governmental interest in criminal accountability
for political and military leaders acting under the
authority of their respective sovereign state? The
impulse to impose such responsibility originated in a
half-hearted way after World War I, with the Versailles
Peace Treaty proposing a criminal prosecution of Kaiser
Wilhelm and a duty by Germany to proceed against lesser
figures in a special court set up at Leipzig. These
initiatives came to nothing, the Kaiser finding asylum in
nearby Holland, and the Leipzig trials exhibiting a lack
of political will by Germany to punish its own nationals.
A serious commitment to criminal accountability arose
after World War II when American diplomacy encouraged a
legal approach to the problem of what to do with
surviving Nazi and Japanese leaders, which seemed
preferable to the prospect of large-scale summary
executions favored by Stalin and Churchill. The Nuremberg
and Tokyo trials went forward, and especially the events
at Nuremberg conveyed to the world the full horror of the
Nazi period to a wide segment of the public. The
experience in Tokyo was more muted, with the prosecuting
powers themselves reluctant to pursue the defendants too
avidly, as Japan was already perceived as an
indispensable ally in the emerging global conflict with
the Soviet Union.
The Nuremberg/Tokyo trials, while spectacular in their
revelations of the depravity of the defendants, were also
dogged by accusations of "victors' justice." There was no
scrutiny permitted of such gross violations of the laws
of war as occurred as a result of the indiscriminate
bombing campaigns waged against German and Japanese
cities, resulting in the deaths of hundreds of thousands
of civilians, nor even more notoriously of the use of
atomic bombs against Hiroshima and Nagasaki. In a famous
promise to the future, the American prosecutor at
Nuremberg, a respected US Supreme Court Justice, Robert
Jackson, acknowledged that unless in the future those who
sat in judgment accepted for themselves the same
standards of accountability as were imposed on the German
defendants, the Nuremberg Judgment would be deeply
discredited from both a legal and political point of
view. The celebrated German philosopher, Karl Jaspers,
echoed these sentiments when confronting the question of
"German war guilt."
We now know that with the onset of the cold war the
effort to impose criminal accountability of governmental
leaders was effectively abandoned. Indeed, the victorious
powers in World War II were each subsequently associated
with wars that included recourse to belligerent tactics
of the sort condemned at Nuremberg and Tokyo. To the
extent that these ideas were kept alive at all, it was a
result of efforts within civil society. The Vietnam War
produced deep splits in democratic societies, including
the United States. Telford Taylor, a former military
officer and an important member of the prosecuting team
at Nuremberg, wrote an influential book late in the
Vietnam War that effectively argued that the policies
being pursued in Vietnam by the United States were in
significant ways comparable to the policies that had been
declared criminal at Nuremberg, providing the basic for
conviction and punishment of Nazi war leaders. In
addition, the British Nobel Prize winner, Bertrand
Russell, established a war crimes tribunal of prominent
intellectual and cultural figures that gathered evidence
and assessed United States responsibility for criminal
conduct in Vietnam, reaching a verdict of guilt. The same
kind of civic impulse led many American to justify a
refusal to participate in the war, by way of the draft or
through taxes, by appealing to what came to be called
"the Nuremberg Obligation," that is, the right of a
citizen to reject the authority of government if "the
law" resulted in violation of the sort of obligations
under international law that had been punished at
Nuremberg. In effect, governments after 1945 ignored the
idea of criminal accountability, and to the extent that
it survived, it was due to the visionary commitments of
citizens acting in defiance of prevailing governmental
policies.
How then can we explain the revival of
inter-governmental interest in the 1990s, especially in
the setting of the war in Bosnia? Such a revival was
officially justified by reference to the occurrence of
"ethnic cleansing" and associated tactics relied upon,
especially on the Serbian side, in Bosnia, leading the UN
Security Council to authorize the creation of the Hague
Tribunal. The context of authorization was significant.
Europe and North America had called attention to the
terrible massacres, mass rapes, and cruelty in Bosnia,
but were unwilling to mount an effective humanitarian
intervention. The UN was authorized to enter Bosnia with
peacekeeping forces, but with insufficient capabilities
and a mission based on impartiality, it stood aside while
ethnic cleansing proceeded apace, culminating in the
slaughter of thousands of Muslims trapped by Serbian
military forces in the UN "safe haven" of Srebrenica. The
failure of the humanitarian effort in Bosnia generated a
sense of guilt on the part of the American and European
leaders, as well as a genuine distaste for what had
occurred. At the same time, there was still very little
political support for action that might be expensive in
lives or resources. In such a setting, imposing economic
sanctions and initiating criminal prosecutions against
the perpetrators, represented geopolitical maneuvers of a
rather cynical character. True, those indicted at The
Hague in the last several years, were fully investigated,
and were responsible for criminal acts, but at the same
time, the leading perpetrators of Bosnian "ethnic
cleansing," Radovan Karadzic and Rakko Mladic, and most
of all Slobodan Milosevic, were not apprehended. Indeed,
Milosevic was not even indicted until the midst of the
1999 NATO air campaign relating to Kosovo, by which time
his usefulness as a negotiating partner for the West was
presumably exhausted.
Transitional Justice for Kosovo
It is important to draw a sharp distinction between
the culpability of the defendants charged and wider
questions of transitional justice for a society that has
experienced intense ethnic conflict over a period of many
years. What is most objectionable about the application
of notions of criminal accountability to former
Yugoslavia is the extent to which the whole project seems
guided by geopolitical motives of a morally dubious
character. These are quite far removed from, and are to a
significant extent, inconsistent with the wellbeing of
the affected Yugoslav peoples that have endured traumas
of varying magnitudes during the 1990s. It is not only a
matter of failing to pursue those most responsible for
the alleged criminality, but the tendency to impose
collective responsibility on one side inflicting
continuing pain and suffering on civilians. By contending
that Milosevic is an indicted war criminal, the NATO
countries, particularly the United States and the United
Kingdom, have justified continuing to maintain harsh
economic sanctions on Serbia, including even the denial
of heating oil for cities facing long, cold winters,
including cities that had distinguished themselves by
opposing Milosevic's rule. In effect, the post-conflict
approach to Belgrade seems to be taking its cruel shape
on the basis of the model relied upon in Iraq since 1991,
inflicting hundreds of thousands of deaths on the most
vulnerable portions of the population. In other words,
the war crimes dimension of the Kosovo War is being
relied upon to continue the war against Serbia, but by
way of sanctions rather than bombs, but possibly with
greater suffering for the people.
Such an impression is reinforced by the occupying
policies and propaganda used in Kosovo since the
ceasefire of several months ago. The UN/NATO peacekeeping
force has been unable (or unwilling) to prevent "ethnic
cleansing" of the Serbian minority, with the result being
that the Serb population has dwindled from 200,000 to
less than 50,000, with those huddled for precarious
safety in villages in the North of Serbia. As Aleksandar
Jovic has noted, the NATO leaders and the media has
subtly excused the post-ceasefire crimes of the KLA and
their supporters in Kosovo by using the terminology of
"reverse ethnic cleansing" and "revenge killing,"
harkening back to a defining moment of provocation that
explains, and even excuses the present slaughter of
innocents under the virtual gaze of the peacekeepers.
Of course, further in the background is the question
of "victors' injustice." There are host of questions that
an impartial international inquiry into criminality of
the events in Kosovo would investigate, including some
difficult challenges directed at NATO. First of all, the
most serious of Nuremberg crimes was viewed as Crimes
against Peace, the waging of aggressive war, that is, the
recourse to force in international affairs without an
adequate legal justification. The UN Charter is very
clear that recourse to enforcement actions by a regional
actor was prohibited unless authorized by the Security
Council. It could be argued in NATO's defense that the
prospect of ethnic cleansing created an emergency
exception and that recourse to the Security Council was
not practical because of the wellknown prospect of China
and Russia vetoing any initiative that called for force
in Kosovo. Such a contention might have made NATO's
action seem legally (and morally) justifiable in the
context of preventing genocide, if a reasonable effort
had been made to find a diplomatic solution. The evidence
currently available suggest that no such effort was made.
On the contrary, prior to the bombing campaign, NATO
insisted that Belgrade accept a series of demands tabled
at Rambouillet that would have involved a deep intrustion
upon Serbian sovereignty. As well, Russia known to be
friendlier to Serbia was excluded from any negotiations,
strengthening the impression that NATO was delivering an
ultimatum, and was interested in any outcome that did not
involve a Serbian surrender.
Such an impression is strengthened by the negotiations
that ended the war, which exhibited the flexibility that
might have avoided the war altogether. The Russian
diplomate, Chernymyrdin, was at the center of the
negotiations, the peacekeeping force was mainly described
as operating under UN auspices, and its writ was limited
to Kosovo. It is indeed strange that the terms for Kosovo
would be more lenient after 78 days of bombing than prior
to the recourse to force. The only reasonable inference
is that NATO wanted to gain credit for a "victory," even
if meant recourse to an "illegal" war.
Such illegality is not a trivial matter. The prime
mission of the United Nations, as signaled in the famous
words of its Preamble, is to "save succeeding generations
from the scourge of war." The constitutional devices
adopted to make such an undertaking plausible was the
Charter prohibition on the use of international force
except in self-defense or under the authority of the
Security Council. Although the role of regional
peacekeeping was incorporated into the Charter it was
subordinated, requiring express authorization in advance
of any enforcement activity. Such a restriction is
obviously important in protecting regional pariahs such
as Israel and Cuba. The point here is that criminal
accountability in the context of Kosovo should include an
investigation of the NATO decision to have recourse to
force.
Such an investigation should also extend to several
legally dubious NATO belligerent practices, including
high-altitude bombing, responsibility for civilian
targeting including extensive pollution causing serious
health hazards, reliance on shells tipped with depleted
uranium and cluster bombs. Such practices appear on their
face inconsistent with existing rules of the laws of
war.
Without such an evenhanded approach to the issue of
criminal accountability, the results are misleading in
the extreme, especially in the setting of a complex
ethnic conflict of the sort that existed for decades, if
not longer, in Kosovo. Two broad sets of considerations
are at stake: subjecting geopolitical actors, such as the
United States and NATO, to the rule of law in their
global activities affecting peace and security; and
ensuring that the outcome of ethnic conflict is not
manipulated in such a way as to resolve it arbitrarily
for the benefit of the side supported by external
military intervention, especially if as here, the
intervention itself seemed in violation of international
law, of the UN Charter, and an instance of a Crime
against Peace.
Conclusion
There is a fundamental difference in the dynamics of
resolving issues of transitional justice between
countries that have experienced an internal process of
conflict that has produced a shift away from
oppressiveness and those, like former Yugoslavia, that
have been the target of extensive military intervention.
In the former, self-determination has produced an outcome
that is negotiated on the basis of perceived mutual
benefit. In the latter instances, the arrangement is
negotiated with powerful outside forces that have a
series of priorities that may not reflect the interests
or power relations of the society whose destiny is being
shaped.
If such arrangements are imposed by an occupying force
after an international war, then it is likely to give
rise to a post-conflict situation in which the element of
criminal accountability is apportioned to the internal
wrongdoers in a relatively convincing manner, as occurred
after World War especially in Germany. However, if the
setting is one of intranational war as in Kosovo (or
Bosnia), and the internal conflict remains unresolved,
the apportionment of blame via procedures for criminal
accountability, is likely to be itself interventionary
and unjust in the sense of not treating equals equally.
As well, it is almost certain to exempt the intervening
side from scrutiny, much less blame.
These various developments are in evidence in Serbia
(including Kosovo). A war prompted to stop ethnic
cleansing in Kosovo has resulted in a new cycle of ethnic
cleansing. A war engaged in to protect the Kosovars has
been continued via sanctions to achieve a change in
governance in Belgrade, despite major burdens being
placed on the civilian population. The acceptance of
Serbian sovereignty over Kosovo has been quietly
undermined by moves in support of de facto Kosovo
independence under the probable authority of an
oppressive Albanian leadership dominated by KLA members.
Not all of these developments were planned by NATO or
Washington, and not all are necessarily worse than
alternatives. For instance, it is certainly legally and
morally arguable that Belgrade since revoking Kosovo
autonomy in 1989 had been responsible for such severe and
systematic violations of the human rights of the Albanian
Kosovar majority population as to have forfeited claims
to exercise sovereignty over the province.
In effect, the merits of how to treat issues of
transitional justice need to be addressed in each
context, with due regard for the wellbeing of affected
peoples. Kosovo is so troubling because this due regard
seems to have been sacrificed all along to the exigencies
of geopolitics, ranging from an interest in keeping NATO
alive in the post-cold war setting to overcoming the
shame of multiple failures in Bosnia, and finally
extending to the illicit idea of fighting a risk-free
"humanitarian war" at the expense of the target
society.
The preceding analysis is not meant as a diatribe
against the revival of efforts to impose criminal
accountability in the setting of transitional justice, or
otherwise. It is intended to underscore the dangers of
exempting geopolitical actors from such accountability,
as well as to demonstrate in the Kosovo setting, the
harmful and distorting consequences of such an exemption.
What such an examination suggests, above all else, is a
principled approach to criminal accountability that is
applied in light of the circumstances of a particular
society. Such an approach is far more difficult to
articulate when the locus of control is situated external
to the society where the alleged criminality has
occurred, especially when the relation of forces in that
society remains unresolved.
The indictment of Milosevic as a war criminal is
emblematic of such difficulties. The timing of the
indictment is, as mentioned, a cause for suspicion,
feeding Serbian beliefs that they were being overly
stigmatized for developments in former Yugoslavia since
1989 compared to other actors. Also, the earlier efforts
of the West to rely on Milosevic to represent Serb
interests in negotiating the end of the Bosnian War in
1995 strongly fosters an impression of Western
opportunism, as Milosevic's instrumental role in
fostering ethnic cleansing in Bosnia was generally known
at the time. By indicting Milosevic while he remained as
head of state also inhibits any process of negotiating a
Chilean transitional solution, and rather than helps the
Serbian people achieve democratic governance,
problematizes both the prospect and imposes on them a
punitive regime of sanctions that is likely to be
life-threatening for vulnerable portions of the
population.
In conclusion, these critical comments are not meant
to exonerate Milosevic or others on the Serb side for
what has occurred in Yugoslavia during the 1990s. There
is every reason to indict, convict, and punish Milosevic
under the proper circumstances. But without such
propriety, his indictment merely continues a cruel
pattern of geopolitical manipulation that is shielded,
even now, from reflection and revision.
© Richard Falk 2000
Tell a friend about this article
Send to:
From:
Message and your name
|