"Humanitarian
Wars," Realist Geopolitics, and Genocidal Practices:
"Saving the Kosovars"

By Richard
Falk
Geopolitics After the Cold War.
The Cold War was generally interpreted as an encounter
between nuclear superpowers that led opposed alliances
and sustained their respective identities by reference to
antagonistic ideologies. Such an image of the global
setting lent support to the argument that international
politics could be best understood from a perspective of
bipolarity. Since the end of the Cold War a decade ago,
and the collapse of the Soviet Union two years later, it
is more difficult to find an illuminating image to
capture the essence of world order. The two main
claimants have been "globalization" and "unipolarity."
Neither image helps us grasp the changing role of the
sovereign state nor the preoccupation during the 1990s
with intrastate violence and conflict, a class of
instances that Mary Kaldor has helpfully dubbed "new
wars."
Partly these concerns reflect a perceived threat to
world order that derives from unexpected sources in
recent years. The main challenges are associated with the
dynamics of "the weak state" unable to sustain order
within its territorial boundaries rather than with the
traditional focus of international relations on the
expansionist machinations of "the strong state." These
latter concerns seem increasingly anachronistic.
It is also necessary to take account of an array of
normative issues (moral and legal) that have been
foregrounded by the socialist collapse. The West, and the
United States in particular, had relied on its supposed
normative superiority to mobilize support at home and
abroad during the Cold War, especially throughout the
1980s endgame. By associating the Soviet "other" with
"the evil empire" it was inevitable that Americans would
project themselves as "the virtuous empire." Not only was
this surge of Manicheanism congenial with the preferred
modality of the binary way that the Western mind works,
but it lent itself to justifying recourse to violence in
a variety of international situations, as well as to
promoting capitalism as the wave of the future á
la Fukuyama.. This sense of a Lockean self came to shape
the identity of many Americans, providing the foundation
for their persisting activism in a world that now lacked
the geopolitical convenience of a strategic enemy. The
most ardent warriors of the Cold War era are continuing
to spend most of their waking hours searching for a new
enemy worthy of geopolitcal stature. In sequence, first
Japan, then Islam, international terrorism, and "the
rogue states," and most recently, China have each been
trotted out before the public as worthy adversaries.
Fortunately, the casting has not been able to produce a
credible enemy, at least not yet. In the absence of an
enemy, the case on behalf of international force poses a
political and conceptual challenge for liberals and
realists alike.
At this point this central geopolitical puzzle remains
unsolved: how to validate the projection of American
military power in the aftermath of the Cold War. What is
worth fighting for in such a world? The Gulf War provided
a partial response: it is worth fighting for oil,
nonproliferation, and the stability of the Middle East,
and further, it is possible to translate military
superiority into political outcomes (the reversal of the
Iraqi conquest of Kuwait, and the elimination of Iraq as
a regional threat) at a minimal cost in casualties. But
Saddam Hussein's aggression was an anomoly for the 1990s,
an international war of expansion that seriously
threatened major interests of regional and global actors.
Such a luxury was unlikely to recur soon!
The emergent challenge associated with the breakdown
of domestic public order of weak states could not often
validate an international response by invoking
traditional realist justifications. Something else was
needed. Into such a strategic vacuum entered a range of
humanitarian concerns, some genuine, others suspect. The
process got started in the form of "humanitarian
peacekeeping" under United Nations auspices, backed by a
Security Council consensus. Somalia came first, then
Bosnia. Both ended in failure, as did the 1994
non-response to large-scale genocide in Rwanda. What went
wrong? Whatever the auspices, interventionary
undertakings with political objectives are likely to be
confronted by violent resistance if perceived by
indigenous political factions to be helping their
domestic adversary. In other words, in Somalia what
started out in 1991 as a humanitarian operation to
overcome famine, disease, and chaos became in its second
phase an effort to establish political order in a
partisan manner, and this immediately engendered
indigenous violent resistance to the UN presence.
In Bosnia, the humanitarian mission was situated in
the midst of an ethnic cleansing campaign of atrocity
that could not simultaneously be both impartial as to the
conflict and effective in protecting the civilian targets
of abuse. The failure of the UN presence to protect
Bosnian civilians even at the "safe haven" of Srebenica
has now been acknowledged in a detailed UN report. It was
not only the complicity of the UN with the agents of
humanitarian catastrophe, but it was the unwillingness of
the members of the Security Council to provide the UN
with the resources required to carry out its assigned
mission. There was both a failure of political will, and
a consensus that was so thin as between the permanent
members that it could be maintained only so long as it
was kept ineffectual in relation to the play of forces at
work.
In Rwanda, coming a year after the backlash in
Somalia, the humanitarian urgency prompted only the most
minimal response at a time when even a relatively minor
effort might have saved hundred of thousands of lives.
There was ample warning of the Hutu plan to commit mass
genocide, and good reasons to believe that a timely UN
augmented response could have made a difference. Again,
the UN failure reflected the refusal of the major states,
especially the United States in this instance, to take
the risks of engagement in Rwanda. The memory of the
breakdown of the Somalia undertaking was too fresh in
Washinton to risk some sort of repetition in Rwanda where
no strategic interests existed.
There are several factors present. The global media as
actor, calling selective attention to humanitarian
catastrophes in a manner that either highlighted or
backgrounded a given situation, influenced the behavior
of key governments. Further, the unipolar structure of
world order, especially with respect to the logistics of
long-distance diplomacy, has meant that the outlook of
the US Government had a decisive influence on what was
undertaken, and how. And finally, the espousal of
international human rights and democracy as major global
agenda items, meant that the idea of territorial
sovereignty, so central to Westphalian notions of
statecraft and written into the UN Charter, were being
significantly eroded. Part of the social contract between
the UN and its member states was that state/society
relations were not subject to UN intervention unless the
Security Council concluded that the situation posed a
serious threat to international peace and security. Such
a development made it conceptually more difficult for
governments to defend the position that severe violations
of the basic rights of their own citizenry were only of
domestic concern. But it also raised understandable
anxieties on the part of countries that were sensitive to
the colonial legacy and were suspicious about the
genunineness of humanitarian claims as being
post-colonial pretexts for renewed Western intervention
in their internal affairs. Such suspicions were
accentuated by the manner in which the United States
exerted an overbearing influence in the Security Council,
as manifested especially in the Gulf War setting. The
domestic jurisdiction limitation on the UN role in peace
and security provided a major source of protection and
reassurance for countries without a right of veto, an
important reassurance given that most members could not
expect consistent participation in, or even access to,
Security Council proceedings.
There are some further structural reasons to be wary
of an endorsement of humanitarian intervention
well-depicted years ago in John Vincent's now classic
study of the doctrine and practice of intervention as a
dimension of Westphalian statecraft.(Vincent,
Nonintervention in International Order, Princeton, 1974).
In brief, Vincent emphasizes the absence of impartial
sources of assessment in relation to the facts in issue
that leads to self-serving interpretations. It might also
be stressed that governments cannot be trusted with
respect to their public justifications for recourse to
international force, tending to stress moral motivations
and to conceal their more selfish strategic goals. Such
mistrust is reinforced by the extensive efforts of
intervening governments to envelop their decisional
processes in secrecy. This pertains particularly to
hegemonic democracies that habitually disguise any
self-seeking and imperialist motives for international
action behind a veil of benevolence. Such a pattern of
considerations is most relevant to an assessment of
American-led humanitarian diplomacy, as the United States
Government depends on strong public approval for its
overseas military undertakings that are not clearly
associated with conventional national interests. These
considerations exert pressure on American leaders to base
humanitarian initiatives on a convincing line of moral
justification, especially when there is no longer a
strategic adversary on the scene. At the same time, as we
shall note in relation to Kosovo, the moralizing
imperative in the absence of strategic threat does not
seem sufficiently compelling to justify the sacrifice of
young American lives.
In the leadup to Kosovo, then, there are a series of
developments that culminated in recourse to the first
"humanitarian war." To begin with, the perceived failure
of UN humanitarian peacekeeping in relation to Somalia,
Bosnia, and Rwanda encouraged a search for a more
effective approach to humanitarian catastrophe. Further,
the acknowledgement of moral guilt by leading governments
in relation to these severe instances of ethnic strife in
the early 1990s, especially in the setting of former
Yugoslavia, made it politically unacceptable to wait on
the sidelines while a new tragedy unfolded in Kosovo.
This consideration was strengthened by the extremely
dirty hands of the West resulting from its earlier
willingness to strike a Faustian Bargain with Milosevic
as a helpful means to find the diplomatic solution to the
Bosnian War at Dayton in 1995. Such factors were given
additional weight due to the American disillusionment
with the United Nations that expressed itself as
hostility toward the Organization by the conservative
majority in the US Congress. And finally, there was
present a widespread sense that European unity in the
1990s could not survive a second round of ethnic
cleansing within its geographic domain, which overlapped
with the complementary concerns that US involvement in
Europe and the viability of NATO depended upon quickly
finding a new raison d'etre.
The mention of such contextual factors is not
tantamount to asserting the impossibility of humanitarian
war in general, or even to discount the relevance of
humanitarian concerns to shaping the international
response to Serb atrocities and state terror in Kosovo
during the months prior to the NATO campaign of 1999.
What is being suggested, however, is the importance of
not too readily accepting a humanitarian rationale for
war. Paul Ricoeur's recommendation of "an ethic of
suspicion" seems especially appropriate whenever the
powerful proclaim that a major use of international force
is "a humanitarian war."
Skepticism about Humanitarian Claims in
Kosovo.
There are further reasons to be skeptical in relation
to the actuality of the NATO response aside from the
generic difficulties associated with accepting the
authenticity of a humanitarian rationale for this
particular war.
--the pre-war diplomacy: one of the most
important efforts of international law is to restrict
uses of force to defensive modes or under UN auspices.
Here, there was neither, allegedly because the Security
Council was blocked by the prospect of Russian and
Chinese vetoes. Under such circumstances, the claim to
prevent genocide or to stop the commission of crimes
against humanity is the essential basis for the
legitimacy of the operation. But recourse to war even
under these exceptional circumstances can only be treated
as an permissible departure from normal restraints on the
use of force only if a maximal effort was made to achieve
a diplomatic solution. The NATO countries contend that
the combination of the efforts at Rambouillet and the
shuttle diplomacy of Richard Holbrooke exhausted all
reasonable efforts to reach an acceptable political
settlement of the dispute. Critics, however, are not
convinced. They wonder why the terms offered Belgrade at
Rambouillet seemed so rigidly insistent on highlighting
the NATO role, which could only be understood as a slap
in the face of Yugoslav sovereignty. They wonder even
more why the diplomacy to end the war brought to the fore
more acceptable negotiators in the persons of
Chernomyrdin and Ahtisaari. They wonder further why the
Russians were allowed such a dominant role in the
post-war peacekeeping, and why the role of NATO was
virtually eclipsed by assigning the formal and
fundamental post-conflict responsibility to the United
Nations. It would seem that had the search for a peaceful
settlement been undertaken in good faith this pattern of
pre-war and post-war diplomacy would have been reversed!
Without access to internal diplomatic communications and
the real objectives of the main players it will be
impossible to gain a conclusive view as to whether the
pre-war diplomacy presupposed that a NATO bluff was
enough to avert war, or that it was believed no
concessions were necessary because even if the bluff did
not work, Belgrade would give in after a few days of
bombing. It seems likely that Milosevic, too, may have
been bluffing, counting on the lack of political will and
unity on the NATO side to persist, at worst, beyond a few
days of bombing..
If appraised by Ricoeur's criterion, it seems
impossible to conclude that NATO upheld its burden of
persuasion. It is not plausible, given the available
evidence, to conclude that recourse to war by NATO
without a UN mandate was primarily motivated by
humanitarian concerns for the Kosovars .
--Conduct of the NATO War. The exclusive
reliance on air power to achieve "victory" in a war
concerning arrangements internal to a sovereign state was
a novelty in the long history of warfare. The
justification for such an approach was premised almost
exclusively on the basis that there was insufficient
political support in NATO countries for any reliance on
ground troops or on strategies that could result in
extensive casualties. In deference to these
considerations, NATO waged a high altitude air campaign
consisting of some 13,000 sorties that produced
considerable "collateral" civilian damage in Serbia and
Kosovo. The civilian infrastructure in former Yugoslavia
was targeted directly after the initial target list
composed of military sites was exhausted after the first
few days of bombing without achieving the expected
response in Belgrade.
Such tactics raise further doubts about the claim of a
humanitarian war. First of all, to shift the risks of
casualties to the side that is being assisted, tarnishes
at the very least the humanitarian dimension of the
undertaking. Such an impression is strengthened by the
total absence of battle casualties on the NATO side, and
the estimated death of some 2000 Kosovars and Serb
civilians. Secondly, the political pressures to avoid
casualties does not exempt the tactics chosen from legal
and moral scrutiny. At most, it suggests that liberal
democracies, given their current political culture, are
unwilling to accept the costs of conducting a
humanitarian war in a humanitarian manner. Further, to
the extent that the tactics relied upon were in violation
of the laws of war, which claim to set minimum guidelines
for warfare to avoid excessive damage and superfluous
suffering, there is a further erosion of the humanitarian
pretension. Thirdly, the targeting of the civilian
infrastructure of former Yugoslavia raises additional
humanitarian concerns.
It does seem correct to take note of an accelerating
pattern of Serb atrocities prior to the war, and the
recourse to a policy of ethnic cleansing almost
immediately upon the onset of the bombing campaign. The
pre-war atrocities are probably best regarded at this
point as expressions of state terror led by Belgrade as
part of its effort to defeat the KLA insurgency rather
than as a distinct plan for ethnic cleansing. The fact
that the NATO bombing appeared to trigger a systematic
plan guided from Belgrade to expel and terrorize the
Albanian population of Kosovo as a whole does not by
itself establish that the war was justified on
humanitarian grounds. It also does not support the view,
that even if the war was initially justified, this
justification was later nullified by the Serbian reaction
that appeared to worsen, at least temporarily, the
humanitarian catastrophe befalling the Albanians. The
relevant test concerns the real motivations and the
extent to which the Serb response was or should have been
anticipated. If the massive Serb terror came as a
surprise, then it does not bear on the evaluation of the
interventionary decision, but if foretold, then it would
add further doubts to those who question the humanitarian
character of the war.
--Concerns after the War. In support of the
humanitarian claim it is important to take note of the
degree to which the Kosovars greeted the NATO-constituted
peacekeeping forces as liberators, as well as the
rapidity with which a large proportion of the refugees
returned to Kosovo despite its devastated conditions.
But it is also necessary to admit the relevance of
Albanian crimes of vengeance directed at the Serb and
Roma minorities in Kosovo despite the KFOR occupying
peacekeeping force and the United Nation UNMIK mission
designed to administer the process of restoring normalcy
to Kosovo. Since the international administration of
Kosovo commenced, a large proportion of the Serb
population has evidently felt obliged to flee from Kosovo
altogether or to retreat from their homes to the northern
part of the province in which there is more protection.
In effect, the goals of a multiethnic Kosovo have been
superseded by the post-war predominance of the KLA and
the Albanian population, and their thinly disguised
intention to turn this transitional period into a process
that results in total political independence for an
Albanian Kosovo. The KLA goal is to avoid either the
emergence of a de facto UN protectorate in Kosovo or the
reintegration of Kosovo into the Federal Republic of
Yugoslavia.
Conclusion
It would be premature at this point to reach
definitive conclusions about the Kosovo experience. At
the same time, certain preliminary assessments can be
made on the basis of what is known. In this spirit, it
does not seem responsible to regard the NATO campaign as
"a humanitarian war." The intervention did appear to
terminate one instance of humanitarian catastrophe,
although it seems to have given rise to a second, lesser
comparable catastrophe directed at the Serbs and Roma
minorities in Kosovo. To be genuinely justifiable as a
humanitarian exception to the UN system governing the use
of force, there needed to be a more diligent effort on
the NATO side to act in good faith within the limits of
international law, as well as a more convincing effort to
choose war only after all reasonable diplomatic
possibilities had been exhausted. Beyond this, the
conduct of the war by NATO and by maintaining sanctions
against Yugoslavia, the postwar diplomacy seemed punitive
toward the Serbian civilian population. It was also
incapable of fulfilling the proclaimed NATO/UN goals of
securing a multiethnic Kosovo that remains within Serbia,
although with a renewal of its autonomous status.
At the same time, a drift toward growing Serb state
terror and genocide was disrupted by the intervention. No
territorial or resource ambitions could be attributed to
the NATO side, thereby strengthening the humanitarian
claims. The Kosovar refugees voted impressively in favor
of the humanitarian interpretation when they returned
massively and voluntarily, exhibiting fulsome gratitude
to the international peacekeepers. The United Nations,
while never endorsing the intervention, held back from
censuring the intervention, and have even appeared to
ratify the outcome by agreeing to play such a pivotal
role in the postwar administration of Kosovo. Further,
the willingness to respond in Kosovo definitely helped
build political support for a UN humanitarian
peacekeeping mission undertaken immediately thereafter
for the sake of the people of East Timor.
Account should also be taken of the fact that the
Kosovo intervention placed the Christian West on the side
of the Albanian Muslim community and in opposition to the
Christian Serbs. Such an alignment is an important
refutation, at least in relation to this conflict, of
Samuel Huntington's thesis that bloody conflicts in the
contemporary world almost inevitably will exhibit "a
clash of civilizations." From what has been argued above,
such an alignment does not by itself establish
humanitarian character of the NATO action, and is quite
consistent with either a geopolitical explanation or with
an analysis that suggests that the political and
ideological realities in the leading NATO countries
precluded a genuine humanitarian undertaking.
What seems to emerge is a complex mixed message. The
prevailing ideas and the dominant actors on the global
stage are not capable of humanitarian warfare if there is
any perceived prospect that they might incur serious
human costs in so doing. For these reasons, to the extent
that genuine humanitarian consideration are involved, as
they were in relation to Kosovo, any action taken is
likely to be either underfunded and insufficient, or to
rely on forms of interventionary violence that are
themselves illegal, and anti-humanitarian. In contrast,
interventions that are reinforced by sufficient political
will and appropriate resources are likely to be only
nominally "humanitarian," and are better understood by
reference to the strategic interests that are at stake
even if these are officially downplayed or denied as the
basis of action.
The precedent of a NATO war without prior Security
Council authorization has already had troublesome
ramifications. The Russians in waging their brutal war
against Chechnya have repeatedly invoked the NATO
precedent, contending with a shred of plausibility that
using force within one's own sovereign territory is less
damaging to world order than the unilateralism of NATO's
war against a foreign country. Of course, there is a
crucial difference. NATO was reacting to widely reported
crimes against humanity and state terror, if not ethnic
cleansing. Moscow is engaged in a war of annihilation to
frustrate the aspirations of the people of Chechnya to
achieve political independence and self-determination in
the face of a long reign of abusive rule, and only
inauthentically basing its action on claims of
counter-terror.
As of the year 2000, it seems structurally impossible
to envision "humanitarian wars" in the future. What is
ideologically likely, and structurally possible, are
humanitarian initiatives pursued as a result of
transnational social pressures, abetted by global media
attention. It is also reasonable to anticipate
"geopolitical interventionary wars" that are validated by
reference to humanitarian concerns. Such is the prospect
in a world where the normative agenda is receiving
growing prominence, but the role of power is still
predominantly determined by the self-help character of a
state-centric world in which security policy is shaped by
realist sensibilities. Such sensibilities remain ill at
ease with humanitarian claims, despite recent rhetorical
pretensions to the contrary, except possibly when
searching for public policy justifications.
© Richard Falk 2000
XII/13/99

Tell a friend about this article
Send to:
From:
Message and your name
|