Review
Zelim Skurbaty's "As If People Mattered"
By Johan
Galtung,
Dr hc mult, Professor of Peace Studies, American,
Granada,
Ritsumeikan, Tromsoe, Witten Universities;
Director, TRANSCEND: A Peace and Development Network
&
TFF associate
AS IF PEOPLES
MATTERED
By Zelim Skurbaty
Published by Kluwer Law International
Martinus Nijhoff Publishers
The Hague/Boston/London, 2000, xxvii + 498pp.
The Raoul Wallenberg Institute Human Rights Library Vol.
4
Dr Skurbaty has written a very important book,
probably destined to become something of a classic. He
draws upon an enormous amount of philosophy, humanities
and social science and footnotes everything, including
his frequent use of Latin.
He is a learned, not only educated, man, up to a level
I have only experienced in academies in the old Soviet
Union, leaning on the older Russian tradition now
disappearing rapidly, yielding to business administration
and computer science there as elsewhere. As a learned man
Skurbaty belongs to an endangered species; his is not the
kind of knowledge picked up by a voracious reader but
knowledge with purpose. He mobilizes his intellectual
apparatus to explore well-mined territory occupied by
international law.
Then there are the many philosophical and social
science excursions, whether read as refresher courses or
as initiation, always important. For him the whole legal
approach is located in the interphase between philosophy
and the "machine" -- the legal machinery, he quotes Le
Corbusier on the house as a machine for living. The
philosophy defines our values, the machine implements
them. And Skurbaty's analysis of how they then proceed to
play games is masterly, using the whole machinery for
non-implementation rather than implementation.
My first doubt centers on the word "our". Where is
this majestic "we"? I see for my inner eye armies of
lawyers, white upper/middle class Western Big Power male
from uniervsities serving the state, and those trained by
them. I smell class, "ours" for sure, in people taking
sleep and toilet so much for granted that they do not
even figure as universal human rights. Take an example:
the Badinter commission on Yugoslavia, quoted at some
length. Imagine they had been courageous and creative
enough to acknowledge the Chinese boxes nature of
"peoples", with peoples within peoples within peoples,
and not so scared by the word-pair secession-independence
that they cannot open for a wide range of types of
autonomy. The Croats had an obvious right to
self-determination, but so do the Serbsin Krajina and
Slavonija (and, problematic for those Serbs, how about
Croat minorities inside those territories?) Being French,
as Skurbaty indicates, they of course had Basques and
Corsicans in mind when they were writing their "opinion"
(a correct term, see p. 257). Uti possidetis, the
disastrous Damocles sword hanging over the whole
self-determination exercise, serves as a protection of
status quo, and was used--possibly with the whole
Yugoslav disaster as a result. The Badinter commission
did a lousy job because they could play that game with
impunity.
The book is not easy reading. But then it can be read
in at least two ways. Each part, each section and
sub-section, is self-contained and conveys enormous,
useful information, for instance his "clinical" cases,
such as Yugoslavia, Palestine, and above all Chechnya.
Or, take footnote 11 on p. 76: the list of 32 peoples
nested inside European nation-states - with very violent,
or distant premonitions of coming struggles between
nationalism for autonomy, sovereignty, even - God forbid
-independence. To me they are like the famous seeds under
asphalt or water in the crevices of a mountain: come
spring and they sprout, come winter and the water
freezes. And the asphalt bursts and so does the mountain
because of some very simple properties of seeds and
water. Well, not always. Smear on layers of asphalt and
granite and some flexibility and it helps. What is this
force? Skurbaty deals not only with peoples, but also
with minorities. For the latter he quotes Asbjoern Eide's
very useful definition pointing to the obvious but often
forgotten: minority is an artihmetic entity, it means
less than half. Why that concern? Because democracy has a
built-in obsession with more than half, called the "will
of the people." If the people is the Sovereign then there
have to be limitations on that sovereign power lest it
ends in despotic absolutism. Hence human rights
protection also in, and for, democracies.
But that is not the end of the story, as Skurbaty's
title, a skilful play on Schumacher's famous "Economics
as if people mattered", indicates. So, what constitutes a
"people"? Well, they are different from people around
them. And they seem to have one simple characteristic in
common that I wish Skurbaty had highlighted more: they
want at least their proximate rulers to be of their own
kind; they detest rule by other peoples. Some of them may
say that to be ruled by their kind at local or district
level is enough and claim autonomy, others may say the
state level is needed and claim independence, still
others, like Americans, want nobody in any form on top of
them, not the UN for instance, and claim universal
sovereignty, highly compatible with building a universal
empire (to want nobody on top can also be a cloak for
wanting to be on top of others.)
Let us face it: given the choice, many people would
prefer being ruled by their own dictator to being ruled
democratically by a majority not of their own kind. To
use a well-known quote: he may be a son-of-a-bitch but he
is our son-of-a-bitch. Human right and democracy will be
seen as a game, one more majority way of legitimizing the
state as a prison of peoples. But most seem to want both:
a democracy, of, for and by their own demos. And that may
spell secession, unless the ruling majority has
sufficient skill to be flexible and work out some scheme
for (con)federation, territorial or--much more
promising--non- territorial. Very often not even that is
needed. Even individual human rights may do: give them
the right to talk their own language and practice their
own religion in private and public space, and the quest
may start withering away. Go one step further, give them
group rights, e.g., to run their own schools in their own
idiom with full recognition and that may be a successful
conflict transformation.
For those believing in humanism and humanist ethics
rather than theism and theocratic ethics the quest for
recognition is satisfied when major rites- naming,
confirmation, wedding, burial--are run by themselves,
their way. Homosexuals are in the early stages of that
struggle. But what happens if humanists, gays and
lesbians want to be governed by their own kind, and only
their own kind?
That quest for religious autonomy was exactly the
pillar on which the USA was founded. But, and Skurbaty
might have given more attention to that, the problem is
not so much that the difficulty defining a people when
they are also playing games (will this definition
destabilize my country?) as the fact that the criteria
are changing. The world may become polyglot and
ecumenical. But that is not the end of the story. New
criteria of people-ness, like sexual orientation, may
come up any time.
One criterion plays a surprisingly minor role in
Skurbaty's dense, rich volume: territorial attachment
(the index has few references to territory). With tourism
being the biggest world industry, and migration a major
fact of life, one may argue that people become
poly-spatial, ecu-territorial. This may be true, but we
are not there yet. There is asynchrony in the world.
Globalized upper/middle class Big Power males, poly-glot,
secularized and poly-jet, may project their sense of non-
ttachment to such "tribal" characteristics as idiom,
faith and territorial attachment to some plains or hills
on the rest of humanity, and proclaim some new universal
principle. But to those others, billions of them, they
look like a power-greedy ayer of global foam floating on
top of the world, attached to nothing but their own
egocentric greed, suffering from advanced anomie (no
compelling values) and atomie (no social tissue).
And that is where my second objection enters:
Skurbaty's use of "individuation". He mentions e pluribus
unum and collective-in-the individual, indicative of
sensitivity to the I-we dialectic. But there are cultures
leaning more to the I side and cultures leaning more to
the we-side. Skurbaty's individuation favors I-cultures
and sounds like a plea for individuals to escape from
collective strait-jackets. The problem is whether this is
not also a plea for anomie (culture-lessness) and atomie
(structure-lessness) in the present reality of
postmodernism, favoring the egocentric cost-benefit
amoral code of economism considerably more than the
Scripture Skurbaty appeals to. Skurbaty might have
benefitted from the literature on Cambodia, a Buddhist
we-culture exposed to a Western I- culture in the form of
Western democracy and individualized human rights that in
the longer run may prove as lethal as the killing fields
of US bombing and the Khmer Rouge. I sense
culture-blindness behind "individuation", added to the
structure-blindness of "our" mentioned above.
But I leave this aside. Skurbaty's book remains a tour
de force. A gold mine of nuggets to be polished for years
to come. Whoever reads the book will be grateful that the
book exists.
Johan Galtung
©
TFF & the author 2001
Tell a friend about this article
Send to:
From:
Message and your name
|