United Nations
reform:
Where is
Kofi Annan's "fork in the road"?
Over the horizon!
By
Richard
Falk
Comments directly to
rfalk@Princeton.edu
December 8, 2006
I. Metaphor and the Politics of Despair
In addressing the General Assembly back in
2003 on the urgent need for UN reform, the Secretary-General of the United
Nations, Kofi Annan, resorted to a frequently quoted metaphorical trope:
“Excellencies, we have come to a fork in the road. This may be a
moment no less decisive than 1945 itself, when the United Nations was
founded.”
He explains the rhetoric by saying “[n]ow we must decide whether
it is possible to continue on the basis agreed upon or whether radical
changes are needed.” And further, Annan notes that he had earlier
“drew attention to the urgent need for the [Security] Council to
regain the confidence of States, and of world public opinion—both
by demonstrating its ability to deal effectively with the most difficult
issues, and by becoming more broadly representative of the international
community as a whole, as well as the geopolitical realities of today.”
[The Secretary General Address to the General Assembly, Sept. 23, 2003,
pp.1-5, at 3]
To build support for the needed radical changes, that is, to ensure that
the right road is chosen at the fork, Annan appointed two panels designed
to shape an agenda for the General Assembly’s reform summit scheduled
for the Fall of 2005, the 60th anniversary of the UN. Both appointed groups
operated according to a realist calculus that tried to take account of
what sorts of changes would be acceptable to a majority of the membership.
The less significant of the two was the Panel of Eminent Persons on UN-Civil
Society Relations, chaired by Fernando Henrique Cardoso, the former President
of Brasil. Its mandate was narrowly framed to encourage proposals that
would give civil society organizations somewhat better access and opportunities
for participation, but within the existing pattern of the UN System. The
127 (?) recommendations of the Panel were rather technical and managerial
in tone, and whether implemented or not, unlikely to alter the basic non-impact
of global civil society on important UN undertakings. [See Falk in GS
Yearbook; Cardoso Report]
The more important initiative was that High-level Panel on Threats, Challenges
and Change that issued a widely discussed report entitled “A more
secure world: Our shared responsibility.” [(New York: The United
Nations, 2004)] In the transmittal letter to the Secretary-General, prefacing
the report, the panel chair, Anand Panyarachun, observes that “[o]ur
mandate from you precluded any in-depth examination of individual conflicts
and we have respected your guidance. But the members of the Panel believe
it would be remiss of them if they failed to point out that no amount
of systemic changes to the way the United Nations handles both old and
new threats to peace and security will enable it to discharge effectively
its role under the Charter if efforts are not redoubled to resolve a number
of long-standing disputes which continue to fester and to feed the new
threats we now face. Foremost among these are the issues of Palestine,
Kashmir and the Korean Peninsula.” [p.xi]
This passages thinly disguises the double bind embedded in the mandate
given to the Panel: who address threats to peace in the current global
setting, but without treading on toes by discussing specific conflicts.
As any inquirer knows, the only way to grasp the general is by attentiveness
to the particular, and this is precisely what is precluded. Hidden here
in the bureaucratic jargon of the UN is the decisive obstacle to the sort
of UN reform that is, indeed, urgently needed if the Organization to realize
the goals of its most ardent supporters and to move in the directions
encouraged by the UN Charter, especially its visionary Preamble. It is
not possible, even in the spirit of advocacy, to take on the most serious
existing breaches of peace and security, or even the most serious proximate
threats.
Despite these restrictions, the Panel does face the new realities of the
twenty-first century in ways worthy of discussion, especially on issues
of peace and security. Three aspects of its approach are illustrative
of its image of reform. Each is situated within a realist calculus of
reformist feasibility, but still lacks serious prospects for implementation
because of a failure to take account of the minefield that makes taking
the road to reform treacherous. The High-level Panel suggests 1) broadening
the idea of security by taking account of the rising support for the concept
of ‘human security,’ and treating issues of disease, poverty,
environmental degradation, and transnational organized crime as falling
within the ambit of security.[21-55] 2) that the new threats to world
order associated either with transnational terrorism or crimes against
humanity/genocide can be addressed within the existing Charter framework
if the right of self-defense as set forth in Article 51 is “properly
understood and applied.” [p.3]
The reformist element here is to insist that
such an extended view of the use of force in self-defense, including its
justifications for preemption and intervention in internal affairs, requires
prior UN Security Council authorization. 3) Following the recommendation
of the Canadian International Commission, an endorsement of “the
emerging norm that there is a collective international responsibility
to protect, exercisable by the Security Council authorizing military intervention
as a last resort, in the event of genocide or other large-scale killing,
ethnic cleansing or serious violation of international humanitarian law
which sovereign Governments have proved powerless or unwilling to prevent.”
[66]
These proposals walk a series of tightropes.
To begin with, the tightrope that allows
the broadening of the idea of security to include threats to human wellbeing
while being respectful of the overarching concern with threats to use
force against a state mounted by state and non-state actors. Overall,
acknowledging geopolitical pressures to engage in preemptive responses
based on the rhetoric of the post-9/11 Bush approach to national security,
while being sensitive to the wider allegations of unilateralism that have
been directed at American foreign policy, especially in the wake of the
Iraq War. They also walk a third tightrope that is responsive to the importance
of the human rights movement that is a high priority for global civil
society while being overtly deferential to the traditional prerogatives
of sovereign states, expressed both by the norm of nonintervention and
by a recognition that international action is only legitimate if the state
fails to address an ongoing humanitarian catastrophe. Each of these moves
seems entirely consistent with the Westphalian concept of world order
based on the interplay of sovereign states, as modified by the development
of international law, and as adapted to a changing global setting.
And yet this agenda is subject to lines of
decisive criticism: the Panel’s proposals go too far given the geopolitical
climate; the proposals are far too modest given the claimed intention
of the reformers to live up to Charter expectations as to collective security
or to safeguard the world against the menace of unilateralism.
Why too far? The United States, in particular, has made it abundantly
clear that it will determine on its own whether to rely on force to address
international conflicts, and without regard to Charter constraints given
its insistence that threats must be dealt with by preventive and preemptive
modes of warfare. As long as the veto is available to the five permanent
members of the Security Council, any effort to impose international restraints
on their behavior depends on their voluntary compliance. And further,
it remains the case that the responsibility to protect is an empty norm
without either endowing the UN with independent capabilities or generating
a political will on the part of leading states to provide needed levels
of support either in advance or in response to humanitarian emergencies.
There is no evidence that such conditions will be met. The feeble response
to the massive genocidal developments in Darfur in the face of the complicity
of the Sudanese government is ample evidence that the political will is
absent to support the norm associated with a responsibility to prevent.
The reformist road advocated by the Panel seems blocked for the foreseeable
future by geopolitical resistance that should have entirely predictable.
Why not far enough? The Panel’s proposals
purport to change policy without altering the constitutional status of
the permanent members within the United Nations and without providing
capabilities and institutional procedures to make their recommendations
assume a meaningful political character. To be more specific, the only
way that the Security Council could be meaningfully empowered to implement
the suggested supervision over extended claims of self-defense is to deny
the availability of the veto to permanent members, but the issue is left
untouched. Similarly, the only way that an interventionary mission to
discharge the responsibility to protect could become credible would be
through the establishment of a UN Emergency Peace Force that was trained
in advance and independently financed and recruited. Again, such an implementing
procedure is not even discussed.
Finally, to make the enlargement of the security
agenda more than words requires some sort of institutional recognition
that these new issues are deserving of inclusion on the agenda of the
Security Council to the same degree as war/peace concerns. Because such
a recognition would highlight the disparity of economic conditions in
the world economy, creating pressures for a more equitable distribution
of the benefits of economic globalization that arises from neoliberal
policies, there is no present prospect that the call for a comprehensive
approach to security will yield behavioral results, except of a kind that
would have been produced in any event, for instance, inter-governmental
cooperation to control transnational organized crime.
For these reasons, the only responsible conclusion
is that the report of the High-level Panel failed from either a realist
perspective of politics as the art of the possible or an idealist perspective
as politics as the quest for the necessary and desirable. Its main proposals,
although carefully formulated and sensitive to the global setting, only
reinforced the mood of despair surrounding issues of global reform.
In this sense, perhaps imprudently, the Panel
accepted an assignment that seems an example of a ‘mission impossible.’
Returning to the fork in the road, there
is no fork, only the old geopolitical pathway dominated by geopolitics
and statism. Kofi Annan’s use of this metaphor is an expression
of false consciousness, especially as related to its animating subject-matter,
which was the combination of American unilateralism with respect to war
making and a general atmosphere of inaction in response to humanitarian
crises. Prior to inserting the metaphor, the Secretary-General calls attention
to the dangerous precedent posed by “this argument” that “States
are not obliged to wait until there is agreement in the Security Council.
Instead, they reserve the right to act unilaterally, or in ad hoc coalitions.”
He adds that “[t]his logic represents a fundamental challenge to
the principles on which, however, imperfectly, world peace and stability
have rested for the last fifty-eight years.”
Annan admits that ‘it is not enough
to denounce unilateralism, unless we also face up squarely to the concerns
that make some States feel uniquely vulnerable, since it is those concerns
that drive them to take unilateral action.”[p.3]
It is here that there is a failure of comprehension,
and an insight into how such a mission impossible is launched. Of course,
the whole discourse is beset by the taboo associated with mentioning particulars,
that is, which state resorted to war for what apparent purpose. It is
obvious from the setting that Annan was talking about the American invasion
of Iraq, but to suggest that this invasion was a response to an American
post-9/11 sense of ‘vulnerability’ is to ignore the overwhelming
evidence that the Iraq War was initiated for reasons of grand strategy,
and the anti-terrorist claims of an imminent threat were trumped up and
quite irrelevant to the policy.
The point here is suggest that if the true
pressures on the UN framework are not properly analyzed there is no way
to fashion a relevant response. The High-level Panel was completely responsive
to the Secretary-General’s mandate, providing momentary cosmetic
relief, but also deflecting a more accurate understanding of the challenge
being mounted against the role of the United Nations Charter by prevailing
patterns of geopolitical behavior.
Decades before the Iraq War, the issue of
Charter obsolescence had been widely discussed. [Perhaps, most notably,
by Thomas Franck in “Who Killed Article 2(4)? Or: Changing Norms
Governing the Use of Force by States,” 64 AJIL 809(1970).] Many
international law specialists have pointed to the practice of states that
cannot be reconciled with Charter constraints on recourse to aggressive
war as an instrument of policy. [See Weisbrod; Arendt & Beck] More
recently, Michael Glennon has been tireless in his critique of what he
regards as ‘legalism,’ even Platonism, contending that it
interferes with a realization that the UN Charter system for restraining
states was never truly implemented as a collective security mechanism,
has not been respected by important states, and lacks constraining weight
and authority. [Michael J. Glennon, “Platonism, Adaptivism, and
Illusion in UN Reform,” Chicago Journal of International Law 6(No.
2):613-640(2006)]
Glennon goes further, lending a provisional
vote of confidence to what he calls “ad hoc coalitions of the willing”
that “provide an effective substitute” “on specific
occasions” for the Security Council, referring to the Kosovo War
launched in 1999 under NATO auspices as his justifying example. He argues
that it was correct to disregard the absence of Security Council authorization
for a non-defensive use of force, and that the NATO authorization, although
not based on international law, was sufficient.[639; see the Report of
the Independent International Commission on Kosovo (Oxford, UK: Oxford
University Press, 2000) for a different approach, pp. 000]
The Kosovo example is misleading as the coalition
of the willing was responding to a credible humanitarian emergency of
limited scope, and not embarking on a geopolitical adventure that rested
neither on moral or political imperatives. To move in Glennon’s
direction is to endorse the geopolitical management of world politics
at a historical moment in which the dominant state enjoys diminishing
respect as a hegemonic actor and confronts deepening resentment arising
from its policies. In this regard to shore up the advocacy of global policy
fashioned by coalitions of the willing by historical reference to the
relative success of the Concert of Europe in keeping the peace in Europe
during the nineteenth century.
At the same time, the prohibition in the
Charter is a key foundation for challenging the legality and legitimacy
of state action by either moderate states or the forces of global civil
society. To the extent that a post-Westphalian form of democratic and
humane global governance is struggling to become a political project it
depends for clarification of its undertaking on the norms associated with
the UN Charter and the Nuremberg tradition of imposing criminal accountability
on leaders of states. [For fuller exposition see Falk, The Declining World
Order (New York: Routledge, 2004); also Falk, Gendzier, and Lifton, eds.,
Crimes of War Iraq (New York: Nation Books, 2006)]
To summarize, the metaphor as used by the
Secretary General to encourage a process of UN reform was influential
in guiding those entrusted with shaping an agenda of proposals and recommendations.
But it was deeply misleading in the sense that it acted as if there existed
an alternative to geopolitics that could be effectively developed by inter-governmental
consensus.
The Secretary-General could have
resigned
Far more appropriate as a metaphorical gesture
of credible substance would have been the resignation of the Secretary-General
precisely because there was no fork in that road! “Without a fork
in the road I cannot continue to serve this world Organization in good
faith!” And elaborating by saying that “due to the recent
circumstances highlighted by the Iraq War, the prevailing path has become
untenable, a betrayal of the core principle of the Charter prohibiting
aggressive war.”
If Kofi Annan, surely a decent person and
dedicated international civil servant had so used the metaphorical moment,
two positive results could be anticipated: first, a wider appreciation
that needed UN reforms of even minimal scope were presently unattainable;
and secondly, a pointed recognition that the United Nations could not
function as intended due to obstructionist tactics of the main geopolitical
actor, the United States.
Such a posture would have given Annan a voice
of his own as well as an audience in civil society that might well have
regarded the occasion of this resignation as an opportune moment to launch
a struggle for the soul of the United Nations.
Whether the path presently being cleared by the more progressive forces
in global civil society is more than a utopian gesture will not be known
for decades, but it is the only path that makes the abolition of aggressive
war, at least potentially, ‘a mission possible.’ Aligning
with this struggle is the only emancipatory option available to those
seeking a humane form of global governance. [See Alain Badiou, Meta-Politics
(London, UK: Verso, 2005)]
The metaphor ‘a fork in the road’
can thus be inverted so as to clarify the historical circumstance, acknowledging
both the absence of choice, from within a Westphalian framing of UN reform,
and the possibility of choice achieved by way of a rupture with standardized
organizational expectations associated with delivering the case for reform
by relying on a rhetoric of urgency that is immediately contradicted by
patterns of performance that submit to the dual disciplines of bureaucratic
inertia and geopolitical discipline.
That the outcome of this dynamic, as evident
in the two reports, whose recommendations were further diluted in the
Secretary-General’s own later report, In Larger Freedom, has been
pathetic from a reformist perspective should not come as a surprise. [In
Larger Freedom: Towards Development, Security and Human Rights for All,
Report of the Secretary General, (New York: United Nations, 2005).] Nor
should the bureaucratic cover up by way of a hollow celebration that pretends
that the meager and marginal steps taken at the World Summit in 2005 responded
adequately, even impressively, to the original urgent call. [“Implementation
of decisions from the 2005 World Summit Outcome for action by the Secretary-General,”
Report of the Secretary-General, 25 Oct 2005, A/60/430.]
What becomes manifest in the course
of this cycle of delusion, is a circular and mutually complicit demonstration
of the exact opposite from what is officially explicated: namely, the
impossibility of UN reform. Acknowledging this impossibility is the only
way to overcome it. To the extent that Kofi Annan, knowingly or unknowingly,
both articulates the urgency of reform and the cover up of its failure,
he is playing the villain’s role in this geopolitical theater of
the absurd.
We are left with Glennon’s overt dismissal
of the UN, and avowal of the primacy of geopolitics, as a more trustworthy
rendering of the global setting in the early twenty-first century than
is the false advertising associated with official UN efforts. [Glennon,
note 00]
In the end, better a counsel of despair than an over-dosage of anti-depressants.
Better only because it prompts resistance that is rooted in the realities
of what exists rather than perpetuating a pattern of escapist delusion.
II. Horizons and Metaphors of Hope
From its inception the United Nations represented
an uneasy Faustian bargain between an idealist search for peace through
law and the realist quest for stability through power. On the idealist
side, is the unconditional prohibition of force except in instances of
self-defense strictly defined to require a prior armed attack, reinforced
by collective security mechanisms that were intended to protect states
that were victims of aggression.
On the realist side, is the grant of veto
power to the five permanent members of the Security Council, further accentuated
by the short-term dependence of the Organization on financial contributions
from member states, especially the leading ones, and by an overall relationship
to the Charter that is premised on voluntary adherence, respectful of
sovereign rights.
Such normative incoherence is bound to generate
disappointment, with idealists expecting too much and realists not expecting
anything at all beyond discussion. The operative impact of this Faustian
bargain has been evident in relation to the Iraq War, with idealists delighted
that the Security Council refused to authorize the invasion in 2003, while
realists bemoaned the irrelevance of the Organization. Subsequent to the
invasion, despite its flagrant violation of the most basis principle of
the Charter, the UN acquiesced in the outcome, lent its support to normalizing
the illegal occupation of the country, and refrained from criticizing
the invasion and occupation.
Through the years, off camera, the UN achieved
many positive results, often beyond most reasonable expectations, and
far beyond what its predecessor, the League of Nations achieved, especially
in such areas as human rights, environmental consciousness, health, care
of children, education, and even in relation to peace and security whenever
geopolitical actors happened to be united in approach. A testimony to
this net contribution to human wellbeing is that no state has withdrawn
from membership in the United Nations over the entire course of its history.
[The one partial exception is Indonesia that withdrew for a year in 1965
to form a counter-organization of ‘new states,’ but returned
after discovering an absence of receptivity to its efforts.]
Given this circumstance, it is not surprising
that the UN reform process is so clogged. There are three sources of resistance
to substantial reform, each quite formidable:
• the amendment process is constitutionally
difficult, and is subject to the veto;
• the entrenched advantages of
some states, and the diverse priorities of different regions, makes
it difficult to achieve a consensus on specific steps (unless innocuous);
• the leading states, especially
the United States, are unwilling to cede control over vital dimension
of global policy or to allow initiatives within the Organization
that express criticism of its global role or specific policies.
With these considerations in mind it is hardly surprising that the
UN has not been able to solve the most pressing demands for the
kind of reform that would provide it with enhanced twenty-first
century legitimacy:
• changing the membership of
the Security Council to take account of shifts in influence since
1945;
• adapting the concept of self-defense
to the current realities of international conflict without giving
states the authority to wage discretionary wars;
• acknowledging the impact of
the global human rights movement to the extent of creating capabilities
and willingness to intervene in internal affairs in reaction to
the threat or actuality of genocide or crimes against humanity;
• taking advantage of the end
of the Cold War to embark upon a path of negotiated nuclear disarmament,
to establish an emergency peace force to deal with humanitarian
emergencies and natural disasters, to establish a global tax that
will provide an independent revenue base, and to create a global
parliament in recognition of the rise of civil society.
It is with this understanding of an agenda
for UN reform that makes it suggestive to rely on the metaphor of ‘horizons’
as clarifying, acknowledging formidable difficulties without being demoralizing.
[Falk, TWQ article on Westphalian pessimists and optimists] A basic distinction
needs to be drawn between horizons of feasibility and horizons of desire.
Horizons of feasibility refer to those adaptations
needed to make the Organization effective and legitimate within its existing
framework, that is, with an acceptance of the normative incoherence associated
with the tension between the Charter as law and geopolitics as practice.
In contrast, horizons of desire, are based
on overcoming this incoherence by minimizing the impact of geopolitics.
This presupposes solving the challenge of global governance by transforming
the United Nations in manner that achieves primacy for the Charter’s
goals and principles.
Such a possibility, currently an impossibility,
would depend on a much more widely shared perception as to the dysfunctionality
of war as an instrument useful for resolving conflict and creating security.
A transformed UN in these directions would provide an institutional foundation
for moral globalization, that is, for the realization of human rights
comprehensively conceived to include economic, social, and cultural rights,
as reinforced by a regime of global law that treated equals equally and
was not beset by claims of exception and by an ethos of nonviolence.
As suggested in the discussion of ‘the
fork in the road’ it would be futile to consider such a transformative
horizoning as relevant to the present or likely discourse on UN reform
within the conventional arenas of statecraft, including the United Nations
itself. Even the horizons of feasibility, other than moves to achieve
managerial efficiencies and marginal adaptations, seem unpromising, although
it is possible to imagine shifts in the political climate that could lead
to adjustments in the makeup of the UN Security Council to make it more
representative or a successful initiative to establish some kind of emergency
force that would give the UN more credibility with respect to interventions
for humanitarian purposes.
If we take account of the recent past, the
most successful reform developments have resulted from ‘coalitions
of the dedicated’ (compare the geopolitical inversion - coalitions
of the willing, as in Kosovo, Iraq) that have been composed of likeminded
governments and a movement of civil society actors. Both the anti-personnel
landmines treaty and the International Criminal Court (ICC) came about
despite the geopolitical resistance led by the United States, and illustrated
the potential reformist capacity of a ‘new internationalism’
that is neither a project of statist nor of global civil society, but
a collaboration that draws strength from this hybrid agency.
Of course, it would be a mistake to attribute
transformative potential to this new internationalism as it is unclear
whether it can move beyond formal successes. The anti-personnel landmines
treaty, while symbolically important, addressed a question of only trivial
relevance to geopolitical goals and the ICC has yet to demonstrate that
it can be a robust contribution to the effort to make individuals who
act for states criminally accountable.
The argument being made is based on an acknowledgement
of the need for UN reform, while trying to rid the quest of false expectations
and empty rhetoric. The metaphor of horizons establishes goals without
regard to political obstacles, and then distinguishes between those goals
that might be achieved by existing mechanisms of influence, horizons of
feasibility, and those goals whose implementation is necessary (and desirable)
but for which there cannot be currently envisioned a successful scenario.
These latter goals of a transformative depth
are thus situated over the horizon. Their pursuit can be understood either
as a new political imaginary for world order in the manner depicted by
Charles Taylor in Modern Social Imaginaries or as a waiting game for the
inevitable breakdown of the Westphalian world order that might convert
a transformation of the United Nations into a political project. [Taylor,
Modern Social Imaginaries (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2004)]
In this regard, it might be recalled that
the League of Nations became a plausible, if flawed, project only after
the devastation of World War I, and the United Nations was only conceivable
in the wake of World War II. Each project was intended to ‘fix’
fundamental deficiencies of world order by shifting the horizons of world
order politics, and each effort moved beyond what seem previously attainable,
yet each fell far short of horizons of desire and longer term necessity.
III. A Concluding Note
Returning to the metaphorical motif,
this essay contends that there is no fork in either road, and that the
metaphor of choice is profoundly misleading and distorting. Within the
United Nations System, as now constituted, there is no reform choice,
and no alternative to the persistence of a geopolitically dominated reality.
Outside the UN, the commitment to UN reform by civil society actors is
the only worthwhile path, although the realization of its vision cannot
even be imagined at this point, but again, there is no choice to be made.
Choosing the geopolitical road to the
future is to close one’s eyes to the near certainty of disaster.
The only road that promises a sustainable and benevolent future now appears
utopian, but given certain unforeseeable developments, could become politically
viable.
Given this assessment, it follows that the
fork in the road metaphor should be rejected. Instead, the reliance on
the metaphor of horizons can be substituted in a dual mode: horizons of
feasibility for reforms within existing structures, and horizons of desire
for transformation that require radically modified structures.
It is the further claim being made here
that both horizons are part of an encompassing social imaginary that can
be named as horizons of necessity.
The perspective is guided by ancient wisdom:
“at the started, they laughed; later on, they began to listen, and
a bit later, they cheered.”
Copyright
© TFF & the author 1997 till today. All rights reserved.
Tell a friend about this TFF
article
Send to:
From:
Message and your name
Get
free TFF articles & updates
|